全文获取类型
收费全文 | 19137篇 |
免费 | 105篇 |
国内免费 | 241篇 |
专业分类
系统科学 | 397篇 |
丛书文集 | 382篇 |
教育与普及 | 73篇 |
理论与方法论 | 73篇 |
现状及发展 | 6482篇 |
研究方法 | 922篇 |
综合类 | 10579篇 |
自然研究 | 575篇 |
出版年
2014年 | 153篇 |
2013年 | 295篇 |
2012年 | 559篇 |
2011年 | 1151篇 |
2010年 | 388篇 |
2009年 | 351篇 |
2008年 | 604篇 |
2007年 | 691篇 |
2006年 | 685篇 |
2005年 | 642篇 |
2004年 | 475篇 |
2003年 | 368篇 |
2002年 | 390篇 |
2001年 | 523篇 |
2000年 | 572篇 |
1999年 | 418篇 |
1992年 | 289篇 |
1991年 | 257篇 |
1990年 | 257篇 |
1989年 | 231篇 |
1988年 | 212篇 |
1987年 | 231篇 |
1986年 | 209篇 |
1985年 | 246篇 |
1984年 | 239篇 |
1983年 | 163篇 |
1982年 | 176篇 |
1981年 | 162篇 |
1980年 | 201篇 |
1979年 | 449篇 |
1978年 | 345篇 |
1977年 | 379篇 |
1976年 | 270篇 |
1975年 | 329篇 |
1974年 | 456篇 |
1973年 | 385篇 |
1972年 | 367篇 |
1971年 | 432篇 |
1970年 | 495篇 |
1969年 | 442篇 |
1968年 | 419篇 |
1967年 | 450篇 |
1966年 | 389篇 |
1965年 | 308篇 |
1959年 | 155篇 |
1958年 | 232篇 |
1957年 | 179篇 |
1956年 | 138篇 |
1955年 | 154篇 |
1954年 | 132篇 |
排序方式: 共有10000条查询结果,搜索用时 25 毫秒
121.
J. L. Heilbron 《Annals of science》2019,76(3-4):387-389
122.
Luiz A. Rocha Joseph D. DiBattista Tane H. Sinclair-Taylor Michael L. Berumen 《Journal of Natural History》2020,54(15-16):1019-1023
ABSTRACT Here we document three cases of mimicry in coral reef fishes not previously reported in the literature involving two groupers (Epinephelus leucogrammicus and Plectropomus marisrubri) and a soapfish (Diploprion drachi) as mimics, and two wrasses (Larabicus quadrilineatus and Cheilinus quinquecinctus) and a blenny (Meiacanthus nigrolineatus) as models. All three cases are of aggressive mimicry, with a predatory species mimicking a harmless one, and in one of the cases, the mimicry is also Müllerian, where both the predator and harmless species are unpalatable. 相似文献
123.
通过对中国大学出版社客户投诉处理工作的抽样调查,分析了大学出版社客户投诉处理工作中的问题以及开展这项工作的现实意义,提出了大学出版社客户投诉处理的对策。 相似文献
124.
Stomata consist of a pair of guard cells that mediate gas and water-vapour exchange between plants and the atmosphere. Stomatal precursor cells-meristemoids-possess a transient stem-cell-like property and undergo several rounds of asymmetric divisions before further differentiation. Here we report that the Arabidopsis thaliana basic helix-loop-helix (bHLH) protein MUTE is a key switch for meristemoid fate transition. In the absence of MUTE, meristemoids abort after excessive asymmetric divisions and fail to differentiate stomata. Constitutive overexpression of MUTE directs the entire epidermis to adopt guard cell identity. MUTE has two paralogues: FAMA, a regulator of guard cell morphogenesis, and SPEECHLESS (SPCH). We show that SPCH directs the first asymmetric division that initiates stomatal lineage. Together, SPCH, MUTE and FAMA bHLH proteins control stomatal development at three consecutive steps: initiation, meristemoid differentiation and guard cell morphogenesis. Our findings highlight the roles of closely related bHLHs in cell type differentiation in plants and animals. 相似文献
125.
126.
127.
Neuronal connectivity is fundamental to information processing in the brain. Therefore, understanding the mechanisms of sensory processing requires uncovering how connection patterns between neurons relate to their function. On a coarse scale, long-range projections can preferentially link cortical regions with similar responses to sensory stimuli. But on the local scale, where dendrites and axons overlap substantially, the functional specificity of connections remains unknown. Here we determine synaptic connectivity between nearby layer 2/3 pyramidal neurons in vitro, the response properties of which were first characterized in mouse visual cortex in vivo. We found that connection probability was related to the similarity of visually driven neuronal activity. Neurons with the same preference for oriented stimuli connected at twice the rate of neurons with orthogonal orientation preferences. Neurons responding similarly to naturalistic stimuli formed connections at much higher rates than those with uncorrelated responses. Bidirectional synaptic connections were found more frequently between neuronal pairs with strongly correlated visual responses. Our results reveal the degree of functional specificity of local synaptic connections in the visual cortex, and point to the existence of fine-scale subnetworks dedicated to processing related sensory information. 相似文献
128.
129.
Taking a cue from remarks Thomas Kuhn makes in 1990 about the historical turn in philosophy of science, I examine the history of history and philosophy of science within parts of the British philosophical context in the 1950s and early 1960s. During this time, ordinary language philosophy's influence was at its peak. I argue that the ordinary language philosophers' methodological recommendation to analyze actual linguistic practice influences several prominent criticisms of the deductive-nomological model of scientific explanation and that these criticisms relate to the historical turn in philosophy of science. To show these connections, I primarily examine the work of Stephen Toulmin, who taught at Oxford from 1949 to 1954, and Michael Scriven, who completed a dissertation on explanation under Gilbert Ryle and R.B. Braithwaite in 1956. I also consider Mary Hesse's appeal to an ordinary language-influenced account of meaning in her account of the role of models and analogies in scientific reasoning, and W.H. Watson's Wittgensteinian philosophy of science, an early influence on Toulmin. I think there are two upshots to my historical sketch. First, it fills out details of the move away from logical positivism to more historical- and practice-focused philosophies of science. Second, questions about linguistic meaning and the proper targets and aims of philosophical analysis are part and parcel of the historical turn, as well as its reception. Looking at the philosophical background during which so-called linguistic philosophers also had a hand in bringing these questions to prominence helps us understand why. 相似文献
130.
In this paper, we shall describe a new account of information in communicational contexts, namely, a causal-deflationary one. Our approach draws from Timpson's deflationary view and supplies the field of philosophy of information with new tools that will help to clarify the underlying structure of communication: information is an abstract entity that must be involved in a causal link in order to achieve communication. In light of our account, communication is not merely the existence of statistical correlations between source and receiver, as usually understood from a purely formal view. Instead, communication is an asymmetric phenomenon involving causal notions: the destination system must be able to be causally manipulated by intervening on the source for successful communication. In a nutshell, we shall support the following lemma: no communication without manipulation. 相似文献